Read The Mind and the Brain Online

Authors: Jeffrey M. Schwartz,Sharon Begley

Tags: #General, #Science

The Mind and the Brain (5 page)

BOOK: The Mind and the Brain
12.56Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Within the scientific if not the philosophical community, the rise of scientific materialism in the midnineteenth century seemed to leave Cartesian dualism in the dust. Materialism not only became the reigning intellectual fashion; it emerged as virtually synonymous with science. In fields from biology to cosmology, science is portrayed as having vanquished the nonmaterial explanations that prescientific cultures advanced for natural phenomena. The mysterious forces once believed to trigger storms have been reduced to permutations of air pressure and temperature. The ghosts behind electric phenomena have been revealed as moving particles. The materialist view of mind holds that there is no more to all this than
neurons doing their electrochemical thing. As Colin McGinn puts it: “This is not because neural processes merely cause conscious processes; it’s because neural processes are conscious processes. Nor is it merely that conscious processes are an aspect of neural processes; it is rather that there is nothing more to a conscious state than its neural correlate.”

The neural connections that form brain circuits are necessary for the existence of mind as we know it. To check this, simply imagine a skull emptied of its brain; when the brain is gone, so are the contents of the mind. Or consider that when the brain is damaged, so is the mind (usually). Or that those neural correlates we’ve been mentioning are undeniably real: when the mind changes, so does the brain (leaving aside which causes which). To some scientists this is all there is, and mind can thus be fully explained by brain, by matter. The materialist conceit holds that brain is all that’s needed—there is no more to the feeling of fear than a tickling of the amygdala, no more to the sound of a whisper than an excitation in the auditory cortex. And there is no more to the sense of free will—the sense that we can choose whether to look left or right, to pick this flower or that, to slip in this CD or that one—than delusion and ignorance about what, exactly, the brain is doing in there. Mind, the theory goes, is just brain with more lyrical allusions. Neural correlates to every aspect of mind you can think of are not merely correlates; they are the essence of that aspect of mind. If introspection tells us otherwise—if it tells us that these “qualia” have an existence and a reality that transcend the crackling and dripping of neurons, and that the power to choose is not illusory—well, then introspection is leading us astray. If introspection tells us that there is more to mind than this, then introspection is flawed. What we think we know about our minds from the inside is wrong, as misguided as an aborigine’s examining a television and concluding that there are living beings inside.

Materialism, it seems fair to say, has neuroscience in a chokehold and has had it there since the nineteenth century. Indeed, there
are those in the neuroscience community whose reductionist bent is so extreme that they have made it their crusade “to eliminate mind language entirely,” as the British neuroscientist Steven Rose bluntly puts it. In other words, notions such as feeling, and memory, and attention, and will—all crucial elements of mind—are to be replaced with neurochemical reactions. This materialist, reductionist camp holds that when we have mapped a mental process to a location in the brain, and when we’ve worked out the sequence of neurochemical releases and uptakes that is associated with it, we have indeed fully explained, and more important understood, the phenomenon in question. Mystery explained. Case closed.

Or is it? Some of the most eminent neuroscientists have questioned the materialist position on the mind-matter enigma. The Canadian neurosurgeon Wilder Penfield, after a long career dedicated to explaining the material basis of mind, in the end decided that brain-related explanations are intrinsically insufficient. Charles Sherrington, the founder of modern neurophysiology, contended in 1947 that brain processes alone cannot account for the full range of subjective mental phenomena, including conscious free will. “That our being should consist of two fundamental elements offers, I suppose, no greater inherent improbability than that it should rest on one only,” he wrote. One of Sherrington’s greatest pupils, Sir John Eccles, held similar views. Eccles won a Nobel Prize for his seminal contributions to our understanding of how nerve cells communicate across synapses, or nerve junctions. In his later years, he worked toward a deeper understanding of the mechanisms mediating the interaction of mind and brain—including the elusive notion of free will. Standard neurobiology tells us that tiny vesicles in the nerve endings contain chemicals called neurotransmitters; in response to an electrical impulse, some of the vesicles release their contents, which cross the synapse and transmit the impulse to the adjoining neuron. In 1986 Eccles proposed that the probability of neurotransmitter release depended on quantum mechanical processes, which can be influenced by the intervention
of the mind. This, Eccles said, provided a basis for the action of a free will.

 

It is fair to say that the debate instigated by Descartes over the mind-body problem has not ended at all; it has instead become almost painfully sophisticated and complex. Among the warring theories in play today we have (in one contemporary rundown) “the identity theory, the central state theory, neutral monism, logical behaviorism, token physicalism and type physicalism, token epiphenomenalism and type epiphenomenalism, anomalous monism, emergent materialism, eliminative materialism, various brands of functionalism”—and, undoubtedly, enough additional isms to assign one to every working philosopher in the world. A few words on a small handful of these philosophies of mind and matter (listed from most to least materialistic) should capture the flavor of the debate and give a sense of the competing ideas.

  • F
    UNCTIONALISM
    , or “Mentalistic Materialism” as the neurosurgeon Joe Bogen has termed it, denies that the mind is anything more than brain states; it is a mere by-product of the brain’s physical activity. As the philosopher Owen Flanagan puts it, “Mental processes are just brain processes,” and understanding what those brain processes are and how they work tells us all there is to know about what mind is. This view recognizes only material influences. Paul and Patricia Churchland and Daniel Dennett are leading advocates of such materialist views, which are closely akin to behaviorism. The materialist position goes so far as to deny the ultimate reality of mental “events” like our color-blind scientist’s sudden experience of the redness of a peony, as well as the actual fact of consciousness itself. Other than the action potentials coursing through brain circuits, they insist, there is nothing more to the workings of the mind—at least, nothing that science needs to address. If we hold tenaciously to such quaint notions as experiential reality, conscious
    ness, and the ontological validity of qualia, it is only out of ignorance: once science parses the actions of the brain in sufficient detail, qualia and consciousness will evaporate just as the “vital spark” did before biologists nailed down the nature of living things. Materialism certainly has one thing going for it. By denying the existence of consciousness and other mental phenomena, it neatly makes the mind-matter problem disappear. No mind, all matter—no mind-matter problem.
  • E
    PIPHENOMENALISM
    acknowledges that mind is a real phenomenon but holds that it cannot have any effect on the physical world. This school acknowledges that mind and matter are two separate beasts, as are physical events and mental events, but only in the sense that qualia and consciousness are not strictly reducible to neuronal events, any more than the properties of water are reducible to the chemical characteristics of oxygen and hydrogen. From this perspective, consciousness is an epiphenomenon of neuronal processes. Epiphenomenalism views the brain as the cause of all aspects of the mind, but because it holds that the physical world is
    causally closed
    —that is, that physical events can have only physical causes—it holds that the mind itself doesn’t actually cause anything to happen that the brain hasn’t already taken care of. It thus leaves us with a rather withered sort of mind, one in which consciousness is, at least in scientific terms, reduced to an impotent shadow of its former self. As a nonphysical phenomenon, it cannot act on the physical world. It cannot make stuff happen. It cannot, say, make an arm move. Epiphenomenalism holds that the brain is the cause of all the mental events in the mind but that the mind itself is not the cause of anything. Because it maintains that the causal arrow points in only one direction, from material to mental, this school denies the causal efficacy of mental states. It therefore finds itself right at home with the fundamental assumption of materialist science, certainly as applied to psychology and now neuroscience, that “mind does not move matter,” as the neurologist
    C. J. Herrick wrote in 1956. Put another way, all physical action can be but the consequence of another physical action. The sense that will and other mental states can move matter—even the matter that makes up one’s own body—is therefore, in the view of the epiphenomenalists, an illusion.
         Although epiphenomenalism is often regarded these days as the only generally acceptable alternative to stark materialism, one problem with this position is that it contradicts our basic core experience that mental states really do affect our actions. To deny the causal efficacy of mental states altogether is to dismiss the experience of willed action as nothing but an illusion. Another critical problem with epiphenomenalism (and other schools that deny the causal efficacy of mind) was raised in 1890 by the psychologist and philosopher William James. The basic principles of evolutionary biology would seem to dictate that any natural phenomenon as prominent in our lives as our experience of consciousness must necessarily have some discernible and quantifiable effect in order for it to exist, and to persist, in nature at all. It must, in other words, confer some selective advantage. And that raises an obvious question: What possible selective advantage could consciousness offer if it is only a functionless phantasm? How could consciousness ever have evolved in the first place if, in and of itself, it does nothing? Why, in short, did nature bother to produce beings capable of self-awareness and subjective, inner experience? True, evolutionary biologists can trot out many examples of traits that have been carried along on the river of evolution although not specifically selected for (the evolutionary biologists Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Lewontin called such traits
    spandrels
    , the architectural term for the elements between the exterior curve of an arch and the right angle of the walls around it, which were not intention-ally built but were instead formed by two architectural traits that were “selected for”). But consciousness seems like an awfully prominent trait not to have been the target of some selection
    pressure. As James put it, “The conclusion that [consciousness] is useful is…quite justifiable. But if it is useful, it must be so through its causal efficaciousness.”
  • E
    MERGENT MATERIALISM
    argues that mind arises from brain in a way that cannot be fully predicted from or reduced to brain processes. The attributes of mind, that is, cannot be explained solely by brain’s physical activity. Further, according to this view, mind may have the power to effect both mental and physical change. Emergentists like Steen Rasmussen suggest that, sometimes, a high-order, emergent property like mind has the power to exert an effect on the lower-order processes that created it. In other words, what emerges can affect what it emerges from.
         The Nobel-winning neuroscientist Roger Sperry taught at the California Institute of Technology from 1954 until his death in 1994. Best known for his study of “split brain” patients (many of whose surgeries severing the connections between the right and left cerebral hemispheres were actually performed by Joe Bogen), Sperry produced the most detailed and scientifically based version of emergent materialism. He variously called his own emergent theory “mentalism,” “emergent mentalism,” or just “the new mentalism.” At first, he argued only that mind is not reducible to cerebral activity, echoing the mainstream emergent position that mind arises from brain as a unique entity whose attributes and power cannot be predicted, or even explained, from its material components alone. But later Sperry became uneasy with the triumph of materialism in neuroscience and what he called its “exclusive ‘bottom-up’ determination of the whole by the parts, in which the neuronal events determine the mental but not vice versa.” As a result he later espoused a view that mental states can indeed have causal efficacy. In contrast to agnostic physicalism (discussed later), which allows mental states to influence other mental states only through the intermediary of the brain, emergent materialism grants to some
    mental states the power directly to change, shape, or bring into being other mental states, as well as to act back on cerebral states. In the years just before his death, Sperry hinted that mental forces could causally shape the electrochemical activity of neurons.
         This represented a radical new vision of the causal relations between higher-order mental processes and neuronal events. What Sperry termed “mental forces” could, he argued, direct the electrochemical traffic between neurons at the cellular level. This view thus argues that emergent mental properties can exert top-down causal control over their component parts—“the downward control by mental events over the lower neuronal events.” This, as we will see in Chapter 2, describes very well the control by an OCD patient’s mind of his neuronal events, specifically the activity in the pathological circuits underlying the disease. Sperry was at pains to point out that his belief did not constitute dualism (that dreaded word!) in any Cartesian sense, but rather a radically revised form of materialism in which the mind is not only emergent but also causal. He maintained (as classical, non-science-based dualists do not) that the myriad conscious experiences cannot exist apart from the brain; he did not posit an unembodied mind or consciousness as, again, classical dualists do. The mental forces he considered causally efficacious were no spooky, nonmaterial, preternatural entities. As he put it in 1970, “The term [mental forces]…does not imply here any disembodied supernatural forces independent of the brain mechanism. The mental forces as here conceived are inseparably tied to the cerebral structure and its functional organization.” They shape and direct the lower-level traffic of electrical impulses. The form of causal efficacy Sperry proposed was one that adherents of materialist, bottom-up determinism dismissed—namely, one in which “higher-level” mental properties exert causal control over the “lower level” of neurons and synapses. In this scheme, Sperry wrote in 1965, “the causal
    potency of an idea, or an ideal, becomes just as real as that of a molecule, a cell, or a nerve impulse.” He fervently hoped that the new view of mind would integrate “traditionally conflicting positions on mind and matter, the mental versus the material,” and that “science as a whole may be in the process of shifting away from its centuries-old microdeterminate materialist paradigm to a more valid macromental model for causal explanation and understanding.”
         Not even a Nobel Prize offered adequate shielding from the brickbats hurled at Sperry for this plunge into the mind-and-matter wars. When the English psychologist Oliver Zangwill visited Caltech in August 1970, as Joe Bogen recounts, he expressed to Sperry his concern that if “Sperry went on in this vein it is likely to diminish the impact of his many marvelous achievements.” How, Bogen asked, did Sperry react? Very little, replied Zangwill. From about 1980, almost all of Sperry’s writings were about consciousness and mental forces acting from the top down. When he was honored at Caltech in 1982 on the occasion of his Nobel, those who had come to know him only recently assumed, recalls Bogen, “that he’s gone religious like so many old folks.” By 1990, even Caltech professors who had known Sperry for four decades “had given up trying to defend or even to understand ‘the philosophy of his later years,’ as one of them put it.”
         Although Sperry put great stress on the reality of the mind in the causal chain, when pressed he seemed to fall back on classical materialist assumptions. He emphatically denied the importance of quantum mechanics for understanding mind-brain relations, insisting that Newtonian physics was entirely up to the task. “It remains true in the mentalist model that the parts…determine the properties of the whole, i.e. microdeter-minism is not abandoned,” he wrote in his last major paper. “The emergent process is…in principle, predictable.” Thus the mental forces he was so fond of referring to were themselves
    determined from below. To those, like me, who were becoming committed to the genuine power of mental force and its integral role in a quantum-based mind-brain theory, Sperry’s views seemed like a refined form of epiphenomenalism.
  • A
    GNOSTIC PHYSICALISM
    also holds that mind derives exclusively from the matter of the brain. In contrast to the epiphenomenalists and functionalists, however, adherents of this school acknowledge that this may not be the whole story. That is what the “agnostic” part reflects: those who subscribe to this worldview do not deny the existence of nonmaterial forces, just as an agnostic does not actively deny the existence of God. Rather, they regard such influences, if they exist, as capable of affecting mental states only as they first influence observable cerebral states. William James falls into this camp. Joe Bogen is careful to distinguish physicalism from materialism. The former holds that the mental does not change without the physical’s (that is, brain states) changing, too. This says nothing about the existence of nonmaterial influences on the mind. It simply asserts that any such influences must work through the brain in order to affect the mind. In contrast, materialism transcends physicalism in actively denying the existence of nonmaterial influences.
         In explaining his own position, Bogen recounts an argument he once had with the philosopher Paul Churchland about the mystery of how brain produces mind, and the need some philosophers and neuroscientists perceive to invoke something immaterial and without spatial extent to affect the brain. Churchland burst out, “Throughout the history of this subject the mind has been considered to be between God and brain. But now you presume to put the brain between God and mind.” To which Bogen replied, “Exactly so, which is how I can be a committed physicalist while remaining agnostic or even indifferent about the immaterial.”
  • P
    ROCESS PHILOSOPHY
    , a school greatly influenced by Alfred North Whitehead, holds that mind and brain are manifestations of a single reality, one that is in constant flux. It thus is compatible with classical Buddhist philosophy, which views clear and penetrating awareness of change and impermanence (
    anicca
    in Pali) as the essence of insight. Thus, as Whitehead put it, “The reality is the process,” and it is a process made up of vital transient “drops of experience, complex and interdependent.” This view is strikingly consistent with recent developments in quantum physics.
  • D
    UALISTIC INTERACTIONISM
    holds that consciousness and other aspects of mind can occur independently of brain. In this view, mental states have the power to shape brain or cerebral states—and, going even further, the mind cannot in any sense be reduced to the brain. Although mind depends on brain for its expression, brain is by its very material nature not sufficient to explain mind completely, for consciousness and everything else lumped under this thing called mind are categorically different beasts from brain and everything else material. John Eccles, who along with the philosopher Karl Popper for many years gallantly championed this view, put it this way not long before his death: “The essential feature of dualist-interactionism is that the mind and brain are independent entities…and that they interact by quantum physics.” Scientists and philosophers in this camp reject materialism to the point of actually positing a nonmaterial basis for the mind. Even worse, they seem to have a penchant for speaking about the possibility of life after death, something no self-respecting scientist is supposed to do in public (although both Eccles and Penfield did). Even scientists and philosophers who question whether simply mapping neural correlates can truly provide the ultimate answer have doubts about dualistic interactionism: neuroscientists may have worlds to go before they understand
    how
    brain gives rise to mind, but even in
    a field not generally marked by certainty they are as sure as sure can be that it does, somehow, manage the trick.
BOOK: The Mind and the Brain
12.56Mb size Format: txt, pdf, ePub
ads

Other books

Mona Lisa Overdrive by William Gibson
The Scarlet Pepper by Dorothy St. James
Hope Rising by Kim Meeder